Product Code Database
Example Keywords: indie games -shirt $42-175
barcode-scavenger
   » » Wiki: Semilattice
Tag Wiki 'Semilattice'.
Tag

In , a join-semilattice (or upper semilattice) is a partially ordered set that has a join (a least upper bound) for any . Dually, a meet-semilattice (or lower semilattice) is a partially ordered set which has a meet (or greatest lower bound) for any nonempty finite subset. Every join-semilattice is a meet-semilattice in the and vice versa.

Semilattices can also be defined : join and meet are , , , and any such operation induces a partial order (and the respective inverse order) such that the result of the operation for any two elements is the least upper bound (or greatest lower bound) of the elements with respect to this partial order.

A lattice is a partially ordered set that is both a meet- and join-semilattice with respect to the same partial order. Algebraically, a lattice is a set with two associative, commutative, idempotent binary operations linked by corresponding .


Order-theoretic definition
A set partially ordered by the is a meet-semilattice if

For all elements and of , the of the set exists.

The greatest lower bound of the set is called the meet of and denoted

Replacing "greatest lower bound" with "" results in the dual concept of a join-semilattice. The least upper bound of is called the join of and , denoted . Meet and join are on A simple induction argument shows that the existence of all possible pairwise suprema (infima), as per the definition, implies the existence of all non-empty finite suprema (infima).

A join-semilattice is bounded if it has a , the join of the empty set. Dually, a meet-semilattice is bounded if it has a , the meet of the empty set.

Other properties may be assumed; see the article on completeness in order theory for more discussion on this subject. That article also discusses how we may rephrase the above definition in terms of the existence of suitable Galois connections between related posets—an approach of special interest for investigations of the concept.


Algebraic definition
A meet-semilattice is an algebraic structure \langle S, \land \rangle consisting of a set with a , called meet, such that for all members and of the following identities hold:

A meet-semilattice \langle S, \land \rangle is bounded if includes an 1 such that for all in

If the symbol , called join, replaces in the definition just given, the structure is called a join-semilattice. One can be ambivalent about the particular choice of symbol for the operation, and speak simply of semilattices.

A semilattice is a , ; i.e., a commutative band. A bounded semilattice is an idempotent commutative .

A partial order is induced on a meet-semilattice by setting whenever . For a join-semilattice, the order is induced by setting whenever . In a bounded meet-semilattice, the identity 1 is the greatest element of Similarly, an identity element in a join semilattice is a least element.


Connection between the two definitions
An order theoretic meet-semilattice gives rise to a such that is an algebraic meet-semilattice. Conversely, the meet-semilattice gives rise to a that partially orders in the following way: for all elements and in if and only if

The relation introduced in this way defines a partial ordering from which the binary operation may be recovered. Conversely, the order induced by the algebraically defined semilattice coincides with that induced by

Hence the two definitions may be used interchangeably, depending on which one is more convenient for a particular purpose. A similar conclusion holds for join-semilattices and the dual ordering ≥.


Examples
Semilattices are employed to construct other order structures, or in conjunction with other completeness properties.
  • A lattice is both a join- and a meet-semilattice. The interaction of these two semilattices via the is what truly distinguishes a lattice from a semilattice.
  • The of an algebraic lattice, under the induced partial ordering, form a bounded join-semilattice.
  • By induction on the number of elements, any non-empty finite meet semilattice has a least element and any non-empty finite join semilattice has a greatest element. (In neither case will the semilattice necessarily be bounded.)
  • A totally ordered set is a distributive lattice, hence in particular a meet-semilattice and join-semilattice: any two distinct elements have a greater and lesser one, which are their meet and join.
    • A is further a bounded join-semilattice, as the set as a whole has a least element, hence it is bounded.
      • The natural numbers \mathbb{N}, with their usual order are a bounded join-semilattice, with least element 0, although they have no greatest element: they are the smallest infinite well-ordered set.
  • Any single-rooted tree (with the single root as the least element) of height \leq \omega is a (generally unbounded) meet-semilattice. Consider for example the set of finite words over some alphabet, ordered by the . It has a least element (the empty word), which is an annihilator element of the meet operation, but no greatest (identity) element.
  • A is a meet-semilattice.
  • Membership in any set can be taken as a of a semilattice with base set because a semilattice captures the essence of set . Let denote & Two sets differing only in one or both of the:
  • Order in which their members are listed;
  • Multiplicity of one or more members,
are in fact the same set. Commutativity and associativity of assure (1), , (2). This semilattice is the over It is not bounded by because a set is not a member of itself.
  • Classical extensional defines a join-semilattice, with join read as binary fusion. This semilattice is bounded from above by the world individual.
  • Given a set the collection of partitions \xi of is a join-semilattice. In fact, the partial order is given by \xi \leq \eta if \forall Q \in \eta, \exists P \in \xi such that Q \subset P and the join of two partitions is given by \xi \vee \eta = \{ P \cap Q \mid P \in \xi \ \land \ Q \in \eta \} . This semilattice is bounded, with the least element being the singleton partition \{ S \} .


Semilattice morphisms
The above algebraic definition of a semilattice suggests a notion of between two semilattices. Given two join-semilattices and , a of (join-) semilattices is a function such that

Hence is just a homomorphism of the two associated with each semilattice. If and both include a least element 0, then should also be a homomorphism, i.e. we additionally require that

In the order-theoretic formulation, these conditions just state that a homomorphism of join-semilattices is a function that preserves binary joins and least elements, if such there be. The obvious dual—replacing with and 0 with 1—transforms this definition of a join-semilattice homomorphism into its meet-semilattice equivalent.

Any semilattice homomorphism is necessarily monotone with respect to the associated ordering relation.


Equivalence with algebraic lattices
There is a well-known equivalence between the category \mathcal{S} of join-semilattices with zero with (\vee,0)-homomorphisms and the category \mathcal{A} of algebraic lattices with -preserving complete join-homomorphisms, as follows. With a join-semilattice S with zero, we associate its ideal lattice \operatorname{Id}\ S. With a (\vee,0)-homomorphism f \colon S \to T of (\vee,0)-semilattices, we associate the map \operatorname{Id}\ f \colon \operatorname{Id}\ S \to \operatorname{Id}\ T, that with any ideal I of S associates the ideal of T generated by f(I). This defines a functor \operatorname{Id} \colon \mathcal{S} \to \mathcal{A}. Conversely, with every algebraic lattice A we associate the (\vee,0)-semilattice K(A) of all of A, and with every compactness-preserving complete join-homomorphism f \colon A \to B between algebraic lattices we associate the restriction K(f) \colon K(A) \to K(B). This defines a functor K \colon \mathcal{A} \to \mathcal{S}. The pair (\operatorname{Id},K) defines a category equivalence between \mathcal{S} and \mathcal{A}.


Distributive semilattices
Surprisingly, there is a notion of "distributivity" applicable to semilattices, even though distributivity conventionally requires the interaction of two binary operations. This notion requires but a single operation, and generalizes the distributivity condition for lattices. A join-semilattice is distributive if for all and with there exist and such that Distributive meet-semilattices are defined dually. These definitions are justified by the fact that any distributive join-semilattice in which binary meets exist is a distributive lattice. See the entry distributivity (order theory).

A join-semilattice is distributive if and only if the lattice of its ideals (under inclusion) is distributive.


Complete semilattices
Nowadays, the term "complete semilattice" has no generally accepted meaning, and various mutually inconsistent definitions exist. If completeness is taken to require the existence of all infinite joins, or all infinite meets, whichever the case may be, as well as finite ones, this immediately leads to partial orders that are in fact . For why the existence of all possible infinite joins entails the existence of all possible infinite meets (and vice versa), see the entry completeness (order theory).

Nevertheless, the literature on occasion still takes complete join- or meet-semilattices to be complete lattices. In this case, "completeness" denotes a restriction on the scope of the . Specifically, a complete join-semilattice requires that the homomorphisms preserve all joins, but contrary to the situation we find for completeness properties, this does not require that homomorphisms preserve all meets. On the other hand, we can conclude that every such mapping is the lower adjoint of some Galois connection. The corresponding (unique) upper adjoint will then be a homomorphism of complete meet-semilattices. This gives rise to a number of useful categorical dualities between the categories of all complete semilattices with morphisms preserving all meets or joins, respectively.

Another usage of "complete meet-semilattice" refers to a cpo. A complete meet-semilattice in this sense is arguably the "most complete" meet-semilattice that is not necessarily a complete lattice. Indeed, a complete meet-semilattice has all non-empty meets (which is equivalent to being bounded complete) and all joins. If such a structure has also a greatest element (the meet of the empty set), it is also a complete lattice. Thus a complete semilattice turns out to be "a complete lattice possibly lacking a top". This definition is of interest specifically in , where bounded complete cpos are studied as . Hence Scott domains have been called algebraic semilattices.

Cardinality-restricted notions of completeness for semilattices have been rarely considered in the literature.E. G. Manes, Algebraic theories, Graduate Texts in Mathematics Volume 26, Springer 1976, p. 57


Free semilattices
This section presupposes some knowledge of . In various situations, semilattices exist. For example, the forgetful functor from the category of join-semilattices (and their homomorphisms) to the of sets (and functions) admits a . Therefore, the free join-semilattice over a set is constructed by taking the collection of all non-empty finite of ordered by subset inclusion. Clearly, can be embedded into by a mapping that takes any element in to the singleton set Then any function from a to a join-semilattice (more formally, to the underlying set of ) induces a unique homomorphism between the join-semilattices and such that Explicitly, is given by f'(A) = \bigvee\{f(s) | s \in A\}. Now the obvious uniqueness of suffices to obtain the required adjunction—the morphism-part of the functor can be derived from general considerations (see ). The case of free meet-semilattices is dual, using the opposite subset inclusion as an ordering. For join-semilattices with bottom, we just add the empty set to the above collection of subsets.

In addition, semilattices often serve as generators for free objects within other categories. Notably, both the forgetful functors from the category of frames and frame-homomorphisms, and from the category of distributive lattices and lattice-homomorphisms, have a left adjoint.


See also
  • generalization of join semilattice


Notes

It is often the case that standard treatments of lattice theory define a semilattice, if that, and then say no more. See the references in the entries and . Moreover, there is no literature on semilattices of comparable magnitude to that on .


External links

Page 1 of 1
1
Page 1 of 1
1

Account

Social:
Pages:  ..   .. 
Items:  .. 

Navigation

General: Atom Feed Atom Feed  .. 
Help:  ..   .. 
Category:  ..   .. 
Media:  ..   .. 
Posts:  ..   ..   .. 

Statistics

Page:  .. 
Summary:  .. 
1 Tags
10/10 Page Rank
5 Page Refs