Ramism was a collection of theories on rhetoric, logic, and pedagogy based on the teachings of Petrus Ramus, a French academic, philosopher, and Huguenot convert, who was murdered during the St. Bartholomew's Day massacre in August 1572.
According to British historian Jonathan Israel:
"Ramism, despite its crudity, enjoyed vast popularity in late sixteenth-century Europe, and at the outset of the seventeenth, providing as it did a method of systematizing all branches of knowledge, emphasizing the relevance of theory to practical applications ..."Jonathan Israel (1995). The Dutch Republic: Its Rise, Greatness and Fall 1477–1806 (1995), p. 582.
He had little effect however on mainstream Switzerland Calvinists, and was largely ignored in Catholic Church countries. Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy (1988), pp. 51–52. The progress of Ramism in the half-century from roughly 1575 to 1625 was closely related to, and mediated by, Higher education: the religious factor came in through the different reception in Protestant and Catholic universities, all over Europe.Bryan S. Turner, Max Weber: Critical Responses (1999), p. 198.
Outside France, for example, there was the 1574 English translation by the Scot Roland MacIlmaine of the University of St Andrews. LLGC.org.ukWilliam Kneale and Martha Kneale, The Development of Logic (1962), p. 302. Ramus's works and influence then appeared in the logical textbooks of the Scotland universities, and equally he had followers in England.
Audomarus Talaeus (Omer Talon) was one early French disciple and writer on Ramism. Virginia.edu The work of Ramus gained early international attention, with Roger Ascham corresponding about him with Johann Sturm, teacher of Ramus and collaborator with Ascham; Ascham supported his stance on Joachim Perion, one early opponent, but also expressed some reservations. Later Ascham found Ramus' lack of respect for Cicero, rather than extreme proponents, just unacceptable.Lawrence V. Ryan, Roger Ascham (1963), pp. 147–8, p. 269.
As late as 1626, Francis Burgersdyk divides the logicians of his day into the Aristotelians, the Ramists and the Semi-Ramists.Michael Losonsky, Language and Logic, in Donald Rutherford (editor), The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy (2006), p. 170.William Kneale and Martha Kneale, The Development of Logic (1962), p. 305. These last endeavoured, like Rudolph Goclenius of Marburg and Amandus Polanus of Basel, to mediate between the contending parties. Ramism was closely linked to systematic Calvinism, but the hybrid Philippo-Ramism (which is where the Semi-Ramists fit in) arose as a blend of Ramus with the logic of Philipp Melanchthon.Michael Losonsky, Language and Logic, in Donald Rutherford (editor), The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy (2006), p. 178.
Where universities were open to Ramist teaching, there still could be dislike and negative reactions, stemming from the perceived personality of Ramus (arrogant, a natural polemicist), or of that of his supporters (young men in a hurry). There was tacit adoption of some of the techniques such as the epitome, without acceptance of the whole package of reform including junking Aristotle in favour of the new textbooks, and making Ramus an authoritative figure. John Rainolds at Oxford was an example of an older academic torn by the issue; his follower Richard Hooker was firmly against "Ramystry".Mordechai Feingold, pp. 289–293 in Nicholas Tyacke (editor), The History of the University of Oxford: Volume IV: Seventeenth-Century Oxford (1984).
Gerhard Johann Vossius at Leiden wrote massive works on classical rhetoric and opposed Ramism. He defended and enriched the Aristotelian tradition for the seventeenth century.George Alexander Kennedy, Classical Rhetoric & Its Christian & Secular Tradition from Ancient to Modern Times (1999), p. 254. He was a representative Dutch opponent; Ramism did not take permanent hold in the universities of the Netherlands, and once William Ames had died, it declined.Willem Frijhoff, Marijke Spies, Dutch Culture in a European Perspective (2004), p. 287.
Mid-century, Ramism was still under attack, from Cartesians such as Johannes Clauberg, who defended Aristotle against Ramus.Edward Craig, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1998), p. 380.
An alternative to this aspect of Ramism, as belated and diminishing, is the discussion initiated by Walter Ong of Ramus in relation to several evolutionary steps. Ong's position, on the importance of Ramus as historical figure and humanist, has been summed up as the center of controversies about method (both in teaching and in scientific discovery) and about rhetoric and logic and their role in communication.Peter Sharratt, Peter Ramus, Walter Ong, and the Tradition of Humanistic Learning, Oral Tradition, 2/1 (1987) pp. 172–87, at p. 173; PDF.
The best known of Ong's theses is Ramus the post-Gutenberg writer, in other words the calibration of the indexing and schematics involved in Ramism to the transition away from written manuscripts, and the spoken word.Jack Goody, The Domestication of the Savage Mind (1977), p. 71. Extensive charts were instead used, drawing on the resources of typography, to organise material, from left to right across a printed page, particularly in theological treatises.Gordon Campbell, The Source of Bunyan's Mapp of Salvation, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, Vol. 44, (1981), pp. 240–241. The cultural impact of Ramism depended on the nexus of printing (trees regularly laid out with curly bracket) and rhetoric, forceful and persuasive at least to some Protestants; and it had partly been anticipated in cataloguing and indexing knowledge and its encyclopedism by Conrad Gesner.Mario Carpo, Architecture in the Age of Printing: Orality, Writing, Typography, and Printed Images in the History of Architectural Theory (2001 translation), p. 110. The term Ramean tree became standard in logic books, applying to the classical Porphyrian tree, or any binary tree, without clear distinction between the underlying structure and the way of displaying it; now scholars use the clearer term Ramist epitome to signify the structure. Ong argued that, a chart being a visual aid and logic having come down to charts, the role of voice and dialogue is placed squarely and rigidly in the domain of rhetoric, and in a lower position.James Crosswhite, The Rhetoric of Reason: Writing and the Attractions of Argument (1996), p. 235.
Two other theses of Ong on Ramism are: the end of copia or profuseness for its own sake in writing, making Ramus an opponent of the Erasmus of ; and the beginning of the later Cartesianism emphasis on clarity. Ong, though, consistently argues that Ramus is thin, insubstantial as a scholar, a beneficiary of fashion supported by the new medium of printing, as well as a transitional figure.Alan Richardson, Ellen Spolsky, The Work of Fiction: Cognition, Culture, and Complexity (2004), p. 121.
These ideas, from the 1950s and 1960s onwards, have been reconsidered. Brian Vickers summed up the view a generation or so later: dismissive of Yates, he notes that bracketed tables existed in older manuscripts, and states that Ong's emphases are found unconvincing. Further, methodus, the Ramists' major slogan, was specific to figures of speech, deriving from Hermogenes of Tarsus via George of Trebizond. And the particular moves used by Ramus in the reconfiguration of rhetoric were in no sense innovative by themselves.Brian Vickers, In Defence of Rhetoric (1988), note p. 65, and pp. 475–7. Lisa Jardine agrees with Ong that he was not a first-rank innovator, more of a successful textbook writer adapting earlier insights centred on topics-logic, but insists on his importance and influence in humanistic logic. She takes the Ramean tree to be a "voguish" pedagogic advance.Lisa Jardine, Humanistic Logic, p. 184–6, in Charles B. Schmitt, Quentin Skinner (editors), The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy (1990), p. 52.
It has been said that:
The need for demarcation was seen in "redundancies and overlapping categories".Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (1996), p. 59.
This was taken to the lengths where it could be mocked in the Port-Royal Logic (1662). There, the authors claimed that "everything that is useful to logic belongs to it", with a swipe at the "torments" the Ramists put themselves through.Jill Vance Burojker (translator and editor), Logic or the Art of Thinking by Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole (1996), p. 12.
The method of demarcation was applied within the trivium, made up of grammar, logic (for which Ramists usually preferred a traditional name, dialectic), and rhetoric. Logic falls, according to Ramus, into two parts: invention (treating of the notion and definition) and judgment (comprising the judgment proper, syllogism and method). In this he was influenced by Rodolphus Agricola.. of Philosophy)] What Ramus does here in fact redefines rhetoric. There is a new configuration, with logic and rhetoric each having two parts: rhetoric was to cover elocutio (mainly figures of speech) and pronuntiatio (oratorical delivery). In general, Ramism liked to deal with as method for organising knowledge.Michael Losonsky, Language and Logic, in Donald Rutherford (editor), The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy (2006), p. 176.
Rhetoric, traditionally, had had five parts, of which inventio (invention) was the first. Two others were dispositio (arrangement) and memoria (memory). Ramus proposed transferring those back to the realm of dialectic (logic); and merging them under a new heading, renaming them as iudicium (judgment).Paolo Rossi, Logic and the Art of Memory (2000 translation), pp. 99–102. This was the final effect: as an intermediate memoria was left with rhetoric.
They comprised the lex veritatis (French du tout, law of truth), lex justitiae ( par soi, law of justice), and lex sapientiae ( universalité, or law of wisdom). The third was in the terms of Ramus "universel premièrement", or to make the universal the first instance. The "wisdom" is therefore to start with the universal, and set up a ramifying binary tree by subdivision. UVA.nlDenis Hollier, R. Howard Bloch, A New History of French Literature (1994), pp. 281–2.
As Ramism evolved, these characteristic binary trees, set up rigidly, were treated differently in various fields. In theology, for example, this procedure was turned on its head, since the search for God, the universal, would appear as the goal rather than the starting point.Brian Cummings, The Literary Culture of the Reformation: Grammar and Grace (2007), p. 258.
Émile Bréhier wrote that after Ramus, "order" as a criterion of the methodical had become commonplace; Descartes needed only to supply to method the idea of relation, exemplified by the idea of a mathematical sequence based on a functional relationship of an element to its successor.Émile Bréhier, The History of Philosophy: The Seventeenth Century (1966 translation), p. 54. Therefore, for Cartesians, the Ramist insights were quite easily absorbed.
For the Baconian method, on the other hand, the rigidity of Ramist distinctions was a serious criticism. Francis Bacon, a Cambridge graduate, was early aware of Ramism, but the near-equation of dispositio with method was unsatisfactory, for Baconians, because arrangement of material was seen to be inadequate for research. The Novum Organum implied in its title a further reform of Aristotle, and its aphorism viii of Book I made this exact point.Brian Vickers, Francis Bacon: The Major Works (2002), p. 342.
William Temple annotated a 1584 reprint of the Dialectics in Cambridge. Concise Dictionary of National Biography Known as an advocate of Ramism, and involved in controversy with Everard Digby of Oxford,Nancy S. Struever, Theory as Practice: Ethical Inquiry in the Renaissance (1992), p. 135. he became secretary to Sir Philip Sidney about a year later, in 1585. Bartleby.com Temple was with Sidney when he died in 1586, and wrote a Latin Ramist commentary on An Apology for Poetry.Roger Howell, Sir Philip Sidney: The Shepherd Knight (1698), p. 113. Sidney himself is supposed to have learned Ramist theory from John Dee, and was the dedicatee of the biography by Banosius, but was not in any strict sense a Ramist.Peter French, John Dee (1972), p. 143.
This Ramist school was influential:
Christopher Marlowe encountered Ramist thought as a student at Cambridge (B.A. in 1584), and made Peter Ramus a character in The Massacre at Paris. He also cited Ramus in Dr. Faustus: Bene disserere est finis logices is a line given to Faustus, who states it is from Aristotle, when it is from the Dialecticae of Ramus..Robert A. Logan. Shakespeare's Marlowe: The Influence of Christopher Marlowe on Shakespeare's Artistry (2007), p. 208.
There is a short treatise by John Milton, who was a student at Christ's from 1625, published two years before his death, called Artis Logicae Plenior Institutio ad Petri Rami Methodum concinnata.Milton's Logic has been translated by Walter J. Ong and Charles J. Ermatinger in Yale University Complete Prose Works of John Milton (1982, 8: 206–408), with an introduction by Ong (144–205). It was one of the last commentaries on Ramist logic.William Bridges Hunter, A Milton Encyclopedia (1978), article Logic and Rhetoric, p. 33. Although composed in the 1640s, it was not published until 1672. Milton, whose first tutor at Christ's William Chappell used Ramist method, can take little enough credit for the content. Most of the text proper is adapted from the 1572 edition of Ramus's logic; most of the commentary is adapted from George Downham's Commentarii in P. Rami Dialecticam (1601)Elizabeth Skerpan-Wheeler, "John Milton (9 December 1608–8? November 1674)," British Rhetoricians and Logicians, 1500–1660, Second Series, volume 281 in the Dictionary of Literary Biography series, Detroit: Thomson Gale, 2003, pp. 188–200 at 195—Downham, also affiliated with Christ's, was a professor of logic at Cambridge. The biography of Ramus is a cut-down version of that of Johann Thomas Freigius (1543–83).
Ramism was built into the curriculum, with the professors required to give Ramist treatments of the trivium. Johannes Piscator anticipated the foundation in writing introductory Ramist texts, Johannes Althusius and Lazarus Schöner likewise wrote respectively on social science topics and mathematics, and Piscator later produced a Ramist theology text.
In 1588 Abraham Fraunce, a protégé of Philip Sidney, published Arcadian Rhetorike, a Ramist-style rhetoric book cut down largely to a discussion of figures of speech (in prose and verse), and referring by its title to Sidney's Arcadia. It was based on a translation of Talon's Rhetoricae, and was a companion to The Lawiers Logike of 1585, an adapted translation of the Dialecticae of Ramus. Through it, Sidney's usage of figures was disseminated as the Ramist "Arcadian rhetoric" of standard English literary components and ornaments, before the source Arcadia had been published. It quickly lent itself to floridity of style. William Wimsatt and Cleanth Brooks consider that the Ramist reform at least created a tension between the ornamented and the plain style (of preachers and scientific scholars), into the seventeenth century, and contributed to the emergence of the latter.William Wimsatt and Cleanth Brooks, Literary Criticism: A Short History (1957), pp. 224–6. With the previous work of Dudley Fenner (1584), and the later book of Charles Butler (1598), Ramist rhetoric in Elizabethan England accepts the reduction to elocutio and pronuntiatio, puts all the emphasis on the former, and reduces its scope to the trope.Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes (1996), p. 62.
Geoffrey Hill classified Robert Burton's Anatomy of Melancholy (1621) as a "post-Ramist anatomy". It is a work (he says against Ong) of a rooted scholar with a "method" but turning Ramism back on itself.Geoffrey Hill, Collected Critical Writings (2008), editor Kenneth Haynes, p. 298 and p. 332.
Samuel Taylor Coleridge combined Aristotelian logic with the Holy Trinity to create his "cinque spotted spider making its way upstream by fits & starts," his logical system based on Ramist logic (thesis, antithesis, synthesis, mesothesis, exothesis).Biographia Literaria, Chapter XIII.
Opposition
Placing Ramism
"It is one of those ironies of history that Peter Ramus, who, in the sixteenth century, thought he was reacting against Aristotelianism by taking memoria from rhetoric and making it part of dialectic, was essentially remaking a move made 300 years before by two Dominican Order professors who were attempting to reshape memorial study in conformity with Aristotle."Carruthers, Mary (1990). The Book of Memory. A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture (1990), p. 153.
Puritans believed the maps proved well suited to rationalize and order the Christian view of revealed truth and the language and knowledge of the new learning, specifically the scientific and philosophical paradigms arising out of the Renaissance.Douglas McKnight, Schooling, the Puritan Imperative, and the Molding of an American National Identity: Education's "errand Into the Wilderness" (2003), p. 53.
Disciplines and demarcations
The aim was a fundamental change of priorities, the transformation of hierarchy of disciplines into a 'circle' of learning, an 'encyclopedia' embracing human culture in all of its richness and concreteness and organized for persuasive transmission to society as a whole. This was the rationale of the Ramist method, which accordingly emphasized mnemonics and pedagogical technique at the expense of discovery and the advancement of learning.Donald R. Kelley, The Beginning of Ideology: Consciousness and society in the French Reformation (1981), p. 141.
Laws and method
At Cambridge
At Herborn
In literature
Ramists
Danish
Dutch
Scottish
English
French
German
Hungarian
Swedish
Swiss
Welsh
Bibliography
External links
|
|